One widely encountered idea today is that there is no black and white when it comes to morality, only a kind of “gray area.” This is often taken to mean that we really can’t know with certainty what is right and wrong, allowing us to “push into the gray” as we make certain moral decisions that at first glance appear to be immoral.
The behavior of the figure of Robin Hood is sometimes mentioned as an example of this “gray area” phenomenon, since he was a character who stole money (morally bad) for the purposes of helping the poor (morally good).
By focusing on the good intentions motivating our choices, and by arguing that morality is ambiguous and mostly “gray” anyway, a person can more easily justify and provide cover for morally problematic actions. When we begin to scrutinize the claim that morality is “gray,” however, we encounter significant problems and contradictions.
The romanticized exploits of Robin Hood, for example, end up providing little more than a “veil of gray” that quickly dissolves when we place ourselves in the situation of the victim of his thievery, having our windows broken and our goods plundered. Those who have been robbed of their possessions often describe, in vivid detail, the awful awareness of personal violation; the crushing of their feeling of security.
In these circumstances, we see the moral problem with Robin Hood’s depraved actions, and appreciate the direct, black and white character of the universal moral injunction against stealing.
Universal moral prohibitions are clearly at the heart of any discussion about the “grayness” of morality. Many human actions, when freely chosen, will always be unacceptable. These actions, referred to as “intrinsic evils,” are immoral regardless of circumstance.
Adultery is an example of an intrinsic evil. Regardless of how much a married man or woman may desire to be with a new romantic flame, and regardless of how terrible his or her current marriage and sex life may appear to be, the decision to have sexual relations with someone who is not his or her spouse will invariably constitute an act of moral depravity on his or her part. Every spouse who has suffered infidelity, and every child who has seen the betrayal of one of their parents by the other can attest that there is no such thing as a “gray zone” for adultery.
Many people who recognize that an action may be black may still be tempted to think that because their intentions are white, the “gray” action may be done. But good intentions cannot bleach the blackness of a deed.
Acknowledging the existence of intrinsic evils and recognizing the binding character of absolute moral prohibitions is an important part of our moral growth and awakening. Indeed, morality itself, as an inner determinant of man’s character, is not fundamentally “gray” at all, but is, by its very nature, a code of black and white.
In the final analysis, the cult of moral grayness is too easily a revolt against fixed and essential moral values. Although fixed moral values must always guide our decisions, correctly applying a general moral principle to a particular situation will often require specific knowledge of the circumstances and details of that situation.
For example, I might have to grapple with the question of whether I have a moral duty to get out of bed and go to work in the morning. Whenever a particular set of circumstances prevail, such as I am healthy; today is a workday; my employer expects me to be present at the workplace; my vehicle is functioning normally, then I would reasonably conclude that I have a moral duty to go to work because of the objective moral commitments I have as a company employee—and, likely, the other employees who would “take up the slack” in my absence. Meanwhile, if I am very sick, I might reasonably conclude that I do not have a moral duty to go to work.
Of course, deciding to stay in bed all day out of mere laziness would constitute an objective failure in terms of my moral duty. The question of my moral duty to go to work, then, is not a “gray area” at all, nor a matter of relative morals, but rather a question of careful discernment, weighing of variables, seeking to do the good and so on.
In sum, the objective lines of our moral obligation may sometimes be difficult to discern, and may even appear gray at first glance, but when we sort out the relevant details and seek to purify our own motives, and become willing to submit to the binding character of absolute moral prohibitions, that gray haze can dissipate, enabling us to see the real moral lines that were there all along.
Father Tadeusz Pacholczyk, Ph.D. earned his doctorate in neuroscience from Yale and did post-doctoral work at Harvard. He is a priest of the diocese of Fall River, MA, and serves as the Director of Education at The National Catholic Bioethics Center in Philadelphia. See www.ncbcenter.org.